Imatges de pàgina
PDF
EPUB

certain cases (that is, in cases of mala prohibita, and not mala in se), from the consent of the offenders. The marquis Beccaria, on the other hand, denies that any such consent can confer the right, and therefore objects to its existence. But the notion of consent is, in nearly all cases, a mere theory, having no foundation in fact. If a foreigner comes into a country, and commits a crime at his first entrance, it is a very forced construction to say that he consents to be bound by its laws. If a pirate commits piracy, it is almost absurd to say that he consents to the right of all nations to punish him for it. The true and rational ground on which the right rests, is not the consent of the offender, but the right of every society to protect its own peace, and interests, and property, and institutions, and the utter want of any right, in other persons, to disturb, or destroy, or subtract them. The right flows, not from consent, but from the legitimate institution of society. If men have a right to form a society for mutual benefit and security, they have a right to punish other persons who would overthrow it. There are many cases where a state authorizes life to be taken away, the lawfulness of which is not doubted. No reasonable man doubts the right of a nation, in a just war, especially of self-defence, to repel force by force, and to take away the lives of its enemies. And this right is not confined to repelling present force, but it extends to precautionary measures, which are necessary for the ultimate safety of the nation. In such a war, a nation may justly insist upon the sacrifice of the lives of its own citizens, however innocent, for the purpose of ensuring its own safety. Accordingly, we find that all nations enrol militia and employ troops for war, and require them to hazard their lives for the preservation of the state. In these cases, life is freely sacrificed by the nation; and the laws enacted for such purposes are deemed just exercises of power. If so, why may not life be taken away by way of punishment, if the safety of society requires it? If a nation may authorize, in war, the destruction of thousands, why may it not authorize the destruction of a single life, if self-preservation require it? The mistake, however, is in supposing that life cannot be taken away without the consent of the party. If the foregoing reasoning is correct, such consent is neither supposed nor necessary. In truth, the supposition of an original compact between all the persons who are subject to the regulations of a society, by their

own free consent, as the necessary and proper basis on which all the rights of such society depend, is, at best, a gratuitous supposition; and it sometimes leads to very incorrect results. It may be added, that the Scriptures most clearly recognize and justify the infliction of capital punishments in certain cases.

2. As to the expediency of capital punishment. This opens a wide field for discussion. Some able men, who do not doubt the right, do still deny the expediency of inflicting it. It may be admitted, that a wise legislature ought to be slow in affixing such a punishment to any but very enormous and dangerous crimes. The frequency of a crime is not, of itself, a sufficient reason for resorting to such a punishment. It should be a crime of great atrocity and danger to society, and which cannot otherwise be effectually guarded against. In affixing punishments to any offence, we should consider what are the objects and ends of punishment. It is clear that capital punishment can have no effect to reform the offender himself. It may have, and ordinarily does have, the effect to deter others from committing a like offence; but, still, human experience shows that even this punishment, when inflicted for small offences, which are easily perpetrated, and to which there is great temptation, does not always operate as an effectual terror. Men sometimes are hardened by the frequent spectacles of capital punishments, and grow indifferent to them. Familiarity deprives them of their horror. The bloodiest codes are not those which have most effectually suppressed offences. Besides, public opinion has great weight in producing the acquittal or condemnation of offenders. If a punishment be grossly disproportionate to the offence, if it shock human feelings, there arises, insensibly, a sympathy for the victim, and a desire to screen him from punishment; so that, as far as certainty of punishment operates to deter from crimes, the object of the legislature is often thus defeated. It may be added, that a reasonable doubt may fairly be entertained, whether any society can lawfully exercise the power of punishing, beyond what the just exigencies of that society require. On the other hand, a total abolition of capital punishments would, in some cases at least, expose society to the chances of deep and vital injuries. A man who has committed murder deliberately, has proved himself unfit for society, and regardless of all the duties which belong to it. In his case, the lex talionis can

hardly be deemed unjust. The safety of society is most effectually guarded by cutting him off from the power of doing further mischief. If his life be not taken away, the only other means left are, confinement for life, or transportation and exile for life. Neither of these is a perfect security against the commission of other crimes, and may not always be within the power of a nation without great inconvenience and great expense to itself. It is true that the latter punishments leave open the chance of reform to the offender, which is, indeed, but too often a mere delusion; but, on the other hand, they greatly diminish the influence of another salutary principle, the deterring of others from committing like crimes. It seems to us, therefore, that it is difficult to maintain the proposition that capital punishments are, at all times and under all circumstances, inexpedient. It may rather be affirmed that, in some cases, they are absolutely indispensable to the safety and good order of society. We should incline to say that, as a general rule, every nation, in its legislation on this subject, must be governed very much by the manners, customs, habits of thinking, and state of opinion, among the people upon whom it is to operate. In a rude and barbarous state of society, summary and almost vindictive punishments seem more necessary than in a highly polished and civilized state of society.

3. As to the crimes to which capital punishments may, most properly, be limited. From what has been already said, this must depend upon the particular circumstances of every age and nation; and much must be left to the exercise of a sound discretion on the part of the legislature. As a general rule, humanity forbids such punishments to be applied to any but crimes of very great enormity, and danger to individuals or the state. If any crimes ean be effectually suppressed by moderate means, these ought, certainly, to be first resorted to. The experience, however, of most nations, if we may judge from the nature and extent of their criminal legislation, seems to disprove the opinion so often indulged by philanthropists, that moderate punishments are sufficient to suppress crimes, and that capital punishments are rarely necessary. The codes of most civilized nations abound with capital punishments. That of Great Britain, a nation in which the public legislation has a deep infusion of popular opinion, is thought to be uncommonly sanguinary. Blackstone, in his Commen

taries (vol. iv, 18), admits that, in his time, not less than one hundred and sixty crimes were, by the English law, punishable with death. In the code of the U. States, only nine crimes are so punishable, viz., treason, murder, arson, rape, robbery of the mail, fraudulent casting away ships, rescue of criminals capitally convicted during execution, and piracy, one species of which is the African slave-trade. In the codes of the several states of the Union, still fewer crimes are generally punishable with death. It remains yet to be proved, whether the general mildness of our penal code has afforded us any greater security against crimes than exists in other nations. Hitherto, the temptations to commit them have been less here, than in other countries less abundantly and cheaply supplied with the necessaries of life. It is still a question, fit to exercise the solicitude and ingenuity of our statesmen and philanthropists, whether we can safely carry on so mild a system in a more corrupt and dense state of society. If we can, it must be by a very sparing use of the power of pardoning; so that the certainty of absolute, unmitigated punishment shall follow upon the offence. Beccaria, with his characteristic humanity and sagacity, has strongly urged that the certainty of punishment is more important to deter from crimes than the severity of it. At present, there is great danger that the pardoning power, in our free forms of government, will, in a great measure, overthrow this salutary principle. Its exercise, therefore, ought to be watched with the greatest jealousy and care, lest the abuse of it should lead to the introduction either of absolute impunity for offences, or of more extensive capital punishments. It will probably be found, from the experience of most nations, that capital punishment ought not wholly to be dispensed with. On the other hand, it may be safely affirmed, that there is no positive necessity to apply it to a very large number of crimes. Treason, murder, arson, piracy, highway robbery, burglary, rape, and some other offences of great enormity, and of a kindred character, are not uncommonly punished in this manner; but beyond these, it is extremely questionable whether there is any necessity or expediency of applying so great a severity. Still, however, as has been already intimated, much must depend upon the opinion and character of the age, and the prevailing habits of the people, and upon the sound exercise of legislative discretion. What may be deemed uselessly severe in one

age or country, may be positively required by the circumstances of another age or country.

4. As to the manner of inflicting the punishment of death. This has been different in different countries, and in different stages of civilization in the same countries. Barbarous nations are generally inclined to severe and vindictive punishments, and, where they punish with death, to aggravate it by prolonging the sufferings of the victim with ingenious devices in cruelty. And even in civilized countries, in cases of a political nature, or of very great atrocity, the punishment has been sometimes inflicted with many horrible accompaniments. Tearing the criminal to pieces, piercing his breast with a pointed pole, pinching to death with redhot pincers, starving him to death, breaking his limbs upon the wheel, pressing him to death in a slow and lingering manner, burning him at the stake, crucifixion, sawing him to pieces, quartering him alive, exposing him to be torn to pieces by wild beasts, and other savage punishments, have been sometimes resorted to for the purposes of vengeance, or public example, or public terror. Compared with these, the infliction of death by drowning, by strangling, by poisoning, by bleeding, by beheading, by shooting, by hanging, is a moderate punishment. In modern times, the public opinion is strongly disposed to discountenance the punishment of death by any but simple means; and the infliction of torture is almost universally reprobated. Even in governments where it is still countenanced by the laws, it is rarely resorted to; and the sentence is remitted, by the policy of the prince, beyond the simple infliction of death. In Prussia, where atrocious criminals are required, by the penal code, to be broken upon the wheel, the king always issues an order to the executioner to strangle the criminal (which is done by a small cord not easily seen) before his limbs are broken. So, in the same country, where larceny, attended with destruction of life, is punished by burning alive, the fagots are so arranged as to form a kind of cell, in which the criminal is suffocated by the fumes of sulphur, or other means, before the flame can reach him. In England, in high treason, the criminal is sentenced to be drawn to the gallows, to be hanged by the neck, and cut down alive, to have his entrails taken out and burned while he is yet alive, to have his head cut off, and his body divided into four parts, and these to be at the king's

disposal. But, generally, all the punishment is remitted by the crown, except the hanging and beheading; and when it is not, by connivance of the officers, the criminal is drawn on a hurdle to the place of execution, and is not disembowelled until actually dead. In other cases, the punishment is now simply by hanging, or, in the military and naval service, by shooting. In France, formerly, the punishment of death was often inflicted by breaking the criminal on the wheel. (Damiens was torn to pieces by horses, after he had been tormented with red-hot pincers, and had suffered other horrid tortures.) The usual punishment now is beheading by the guillotine. In cases of parricide, the criminal is conducted, barefooted, and covered with a black veil, to the place of execution, where his right hand is cut off just before he is beheaded. In Austria, the general mode of punishment is by hanging. In Prussia, hanging is rarely inflicted; but the usual punishment is beheading with a heavy axe, the criminal's head being first tied to a block. In other German states, the uncertain mode of execution by the sword still exists. Sand was executed in this manner. It should be remarked, however, that, in Germany, hanging has always been deemed the most infamous sort of punishment; and the sentence has often been commuted for beheading by the sword, as a milder mode of punishment. In the U. States of America, hanging is the universal mode of capital punishment; and, indeed, the constitution of the U. States contains a provision, declaring that "cruel and unusual punishments shall not be inflicted." In China, murderers are cut to pieces; robbers, not. In Russia, the punishment of death has been frequently inflicted by the knout. In Turkey, strangling, and sewing the criminal up in a bag, and throwing him into the sea, are common modes of punishment. In the Roman code, many severe and cruel punishments were prescribed. During the favored times of the republic, many of these were abolished or mitigated. But again, under the emperors, they were revived with full severity. In the ancient Grecian states, the modes of punishment were also severe, and often cruel. But the most general mode of punishment, in ordinary cases, seems, both in Greece and Rome, to have been by hanging. Whether the ancient Greek mode of capital punishment, by taking poison at such hour as the condemned party should choose, has ever been adopted in any modern nation, we

DEATH, PUNISHMENT OF-DEBTOR AND CREDITOR.

are unable to say. As far as we have been able to learn, it is not in use among any Christian people; and the idea of suicide connected with it would probably prevent any such nation from adopting it. Whether executions ought to be in public or in private, has been a question much discussed, and upon which a great diversity of opinion exists among intelligent statesmen. On the one hand, it is said that public spectacles of this sort have a tendency to brutalize and harden the people, or to make them indifferent to the punishment; and the courage and firmness, with which the criminal often meets death, have a tendency to awaken feelings of sympathy, and even of admiration, and to take away much of the horror of the offence, as well as of the punishment. On the other hand, it is said that the great influence of punishment, in deterring others from the like offence, cannot be obtained in any other way. It is the only means to bring home to the mass of the people a salutary dread and warning; and it is a public admonition of the certainty of punishment following upon crimes. It is also added, that all punishments ought to be subjected to the public scrutiny, so that it may be known that all the law requires, and no more, has been done. If punishments were inflicted in private, it could never be known whether they were justly and properly inflicted upon the persons condemned; or whether, indeed, innocent persons might not become the victims.

In England, the court before which the trial is had, declares the sentence, and directs the execution of it; and its warrant is a sufficient authority to the proper officer to execute it. In the courts of the U. States, there is a like authority; but in the laws of many of the states, there is a provision that the execution shall not take place except by a warrant from the governor, or other executive authority. In cases of murder and other atrocious crimes, the punishment in England is usually inflicted at a very short interval after the sentence. In America, there is usually allowed a very considerable interval, varying from one month to six months. In England and America, there lies no appeal from the verdict of a jury and the sentence of a court, in capital cases. In France, there may be a review of it in the court of cassation. (q. v.) In Germany, there is, in criminal as in civil cases, a right of appeal; hence, in that country, few innocent persons have suffered capitally since the 16th century; and in England 13

VOL. IV.

145

and America, the very fact that the verdict and sentence are final, produces great caution and deliberation in the administration of criminal justice, and a strong leaning towards the prisoner on trial. Capital punishment cannot be inflicted, by the general humanity of the laws of modern nations, upon persons who are insane or who are pregnant, until the latter are delivered and the former become sane. It is said that Frederic the Great required all judgments of his courts, condemning persons to death, to be written on blue paper; thus he was constantly reminded of them as they lay on his table among other papers, from which they were readily distinguished. He usually took a long time to consider such cases, and thus set an excellent example to sovereigns of their duty.

DEATH-WATCH; a species of termes, so called on account of an old superstition that its beating or ticking in a sick room is a sure sign of death.

DEBENTURE. (See Drawback.)

Debt, NATIONAL. (See National Debt.) DEBTOR AND CREDITOR, LAWS OF. One of the first steps, in a community, towards industry and wealth, is the institution of the individual right to property. The guarantee of the individual's earnings to himself is the strongest stimulus to his exertions; and this measure is so obvious, and the one in which every member of a community has so evident an interest, that it is of universal adoption among rude as well as civilized nations, and even precedes the establishment of a regular government; for men will sell, and, as far as they are able, enforce their exclusive right to the fruits of their own labor, before they are in a condition to establish general laws. But, though this principle is so obviously just, and of so early adoption, its extension and application to complicated affairs, and various species of property, and divisions, and modifications of rights to, and interest in, possessions of all sorts, are among the most difficult subjects of legislation. The right of property being once established, the conditions on which the owner will part with and transfer it are, as a natural and necessary consequence, left to his own determination, with some few exceptions; especially one usually made in favor of the government, or, rather, of the whole collective community, who reserve the right of taking individual property for the public use, without the consent of the proprietor, and upon such terms as the government itself shall prescribe. But, even in this case, a debt or obligation on the

part of the government or community arises in favor of the proprietor whose property has been taken. So that we may lay it down as a general doctrine, that, where one parts with and transfers to another any property, or right, of which, by the laws of the community, he was exclusively possessed, this transfer is the basis or meritorious consideration of a promise or obligation on the part of the person to whom the transfer is made, to return some equivalent, or what may be agreed on as an equivalent by the parties. Whether this return be stipulated for in money, lands, goods, or personal services, or any thing of which the value can be estimated, is immaterial in respect to the force of the obligation, which will be the same in either case. The validity of the obligation thus arising is recognised by the laws of all civilized states. But, then, the question arises-and it is one which has much perplexed legislators-What degree of force or sacredness shall be assigned to this obligation, and by what sanctions and penalties shall it be guarded? The personal rights of citizens are, in general, more scrupulously guarded and vindicated by the laws, than those of property, or those the value of which, in money or exchange, admits of an exact estimate. The lives of men, for instance, are generally protected by inflicting the extreme penalty of death for the crime of murder. Such a punishment is only commensurate with the crime, and its justice is universally acknowledged; but a law which should inflict the same punishment for a mere assault on the person, attended by no serious injury, would excite the abhorrence of all men; for, though men are under an undoubted obligation not to commit an unprovoked assault, though not attended by a serious wound, yet such a penalty would be at once pronounced to be out of all proportion to the force and sacredness of the obligation which it would be designed to protect. The question then occurs-How forcible, how binding, how sacred, is this promise and obligation to pay a sum of money or deliver an article of property? Is it so sacred that the debtor ought to be put to death, sent to the galleys, put into the pillory, or the stocks, or whipped, or imprisoned, in case of his failing to fulfil it? In one point all communities agree, namely, as far as the property of the debtor goes, it ought to answer to this obligation; for the value he has received has been absorbed in that which he possesses, and constitutes a part of its amount, or, at least, may

be presumed to have contributed to it. In short, the property of the debtor may be considered to belong to his creditors, to the extent of their demands. The laws of different countries, accordingly, agree in the principle that the creditor shall have the means of getting possession and disposing of the debtor's property to satisfy his demands. The bounds prescribed for the exercise of this well established and universally acknowledged right, vary very considerably in different countries and periods. As long ago as the time of Solon, the necessary implements of husbandry were exempted from this right. The civil law makes an exemption of necessary implements of trade and articles of furniture, and this distinction is adopted very generally, if not universally, throughout the civilized world. The right of the creditor, then, according to the laws and practice of the whole civilized world, does not extend to the whole of the property and possessions of the debtor; and the exception affords a rule for measuring the extent and force of this obligation of debt, in the general estimation of nations; since, in enforcing this obligation, all the laws in this respect stop at the point where individual suffering commences. Though the law adopts the principle, that the goods of the debtor, in effect, belong to the creditor, yet it makes a compromise, even of this right, between the creditor, and debtor, and the community; for the community may be said to be affected by, and to feel the distresses or good fortune of every one of its members; and, accordingly, the creditor is here made to compromise his rights as a creditor, out of regard to his obligations as a member of the community. The law says to him, "Though you strictly have a right to the tools your debtor uses, the clothes he and his family wear, and the beds they sleep upon-for they may have been procured by the very money or goods from which the debt arose ; yet, on the other hand, you owe some obligations to the community, and the community has some obligations to your debtor; you shall not, therefore, turn him and his family naked into the streets, even by reclaiming the very articles you may have sold him." Such is the limit which the laws have, by general consent, put to the extent of the creditor's right over the debtor's property; and, to this extent, every code ought to give as easy, cheap and expeditious a remedy as can be allowed consistently with a just settlement of the validity and amount of the creditor's claim; and such a remedy it is the object of legislators

« AnteriorContinua »